Coercion and Motivations in the Economic Sphere (Deconstructing Coercion, Pt. 3)

Now that we have outlined the general motivations for human action, how do these function in different spheres of human life?  (I will not, of course, be comprehensive here and try to cover the entire scope of human life!)  

In most people’s conception, and certainly in the “Christian libertarian” (for lack of a better term) conception, the religious sphere is governed primarily by the love motivation, the economic sphere is governed primarily by the reward motivation, and the political sphere is governed primarily by the fear motivation: we obey God because we love Him, we obey our boss because he will pay us, and we obey the government because we don’t want it to kill us.  (Hate could also enter into any of these spheres, and I will give brief attention to its role in the economic sphere and a bit more attention to its role in the political sphere.) 

However, as I think is apparent already in that quick summary, this is dangerously oversimplistic.  The example just given above about serving God shows the complexity of motivations even in the religious sphere, a sphere from which even the coercive element does not seem entirely absent.  (This is a contentious subject, and not one I want to enter into here, but inasmuch as leaders of the Church are entrusted with the power of binding and loosing, the exercise of church discipline has a coercive character–it moves to action by the motive of fear–at the very least fear of losing fellowship, at the most, fear of losing salvation.)

The economic sphere is certainly more complex.  First, briefly, the most marginal motivation in the economic sphere, it seems to me, is hate.  Of course, it is quite possible that I could hate someone enough that I would refuse to sell to them.  This was common in the age of segregation and still is in regions charged with racial conflict; classical economists claim that good economic sense will automatically overcome such behavior, but this is to underestimate the power of irrational hate.  Or I could hate someone enough that I would go buy from their competitor even when it didn’t make economic sense, or hate someone enough to refuse to employ them.  However, it is worth noting that in each of these cases, hate doesn’t really motivate an economic action as such; it motivates a refusal of an economic action: I won’t buy, I won’t sell, I won’t employ.  So we might consider hate as an occasional but relatively infrequent intrusion upon the economic sphere, rather than something which characterizes it.  

If we cannot exclude hate as a possible motivation in the economic sphere, then we certainly cannot exclude love, however much we may tend to view the realm of love and the realm of contract as mutually exclusively.  Most obviously, I might often buy things out of love for others.  But on a larger scale, could I not, for instance see my neighbors in desperate need of some good that I am able to provide, and so start up a business out of a desire to help them and provide it for them?  Defenders of capitalism often speak in this way–the entrepreneur identifies a need, and develops a business to serve it–however, they do not really believe this provides the true motivation for the entrepreneur; instead, it is the profit motive, which is to say reward.  Adam Smith of course said it most famously: “It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest.”  This has been a pillar of capitalist theory since–we must expect people to work, buy, and sell chiefly because of the benefit to themselves that they expect.  Within reason, of course, there is nothing terribly wrong with this, but if the reward motivation completely detaches itself from any love motivation–if I seek my own self-interest without any regard to that of others, then we will soon have a very ugly situation on our hands.   

For my purposes here, though, I want to take chief note of how the reward motivation, which I acknowledge to be the dominant one in economics, can easily become distorted into a fear motivation.  Consider someone happily working at a small company–he does his job, to be sure, out of a desire for a paycheck, and perhaps does it well because he wants a bonus.  Of course, he will probably be a better worker if there is an element of love as well–if he really likes his boss, and wants to please him, and if he thinks the work he is doing is valuable.  A new manager takes over, and efficiency is the name of the game (I’m imagining an Office Space sort of situation here).  Workers are afraid of getting laid off.  The motivation to work because of desire to get a paycheck has changed into a motivation to work because of fear of not getting a paycheck.  And as the movie Office Space shows, once this becomes the dominant motivation, you have a very unhealthy work environment.  Moreover, I would submit that once this happens, we have a subtly coercive work environment.  Now, the free marketeer will object and insist that we have a perfectly voluntary system here, because no one is under any legal compulsion–the employees are perfectly free to choose not to work.  However, the free marketeers believe that if someone is legally required to do something, on pain of receiving a steep fine, then this is coercive.  Now, what, I must ask, is the material difference between these two situations?  If someone acts in a certain way because they are afraid of the severe financial consequences of acting otherwise (in losing their job), how is this different from someone who acts in a certain way because they are afraid of the severe financial consequences of acting otherwise (in paying a steep fine)?  

 The coercion, of course, becomes less and less subtle the more desperate the situation of the employee.  If the employee has plenty of independent means, he is unlikely to be very intimidated by threats of losing his job.  Indeed, if the work situation becomes too unpleasant, he will probably just quit.  A typical middle-class worker has a lot more cause to fear unemployment than a wealthy person, but given an unpleasant enough work situation, he will probably take his chances and quit, and try to get a job elsewhere.  Someone who is dirt-poor, isolated, and unsure of the chances of getting any other work may, through terrible fear, put up with the most horrific work conditions lest things become even more horrific by losing his job.  This of course happens all around the Third World, and more often than we care to think in the First.  And yet our free marketeers will insist that this remains a perfectly voluntary arrangement.  But, as soon as any legal strictures are brought into the picture, be they the tiniest fines or penalties, capable of inducing much less fear and much less severe consequences, they decry these as “coercion.”  

 So, coercion is undeniably a reality in employment.  What about in buying and selling?  Here, the fear motivation is rarely as strong, because it is rare that any single purchase will have ramifications as great as the loss or maintenance of employment.  Of course, there are certainly exceptions.  In large enough purchases, so large that the merchant or manufacturer’s livelihood depends on them, or in desperate circumstances, the buyer can gain a great deal of leverage over the seller.  The seller absolutely must make some large sale or face bankruptcy, and so the potential buyer is able to play on this fear and wield great power over the seller, forcing him to agree to terms that he would not normally accept and that we would not normally consider just.   Inasmuch as in this situation persuasion now takes place through fear, we have a coercive situation.  Of course, this may not be morally objectionable.  Perhaps the shopkeeper made several very foolish gambles, and that’s why he is in such straits.  If no one is willing to buy his product except at very unsatisfactory terms, that is perhaps his fault and not theirs.  However, we can certainly envision situations in which the seller is genuinely a victim.  Wal-Mart, for instance, is well-known for strong-arming small producers through its enormous buying power in some pretty unsavory ways. 

What about buying?  This is the part that interests me the most, because of the great increase in the sophistication of coercion that modern marketing has introduced.  In buying, there has always been a potential fear motivation, the fear of starvation, illness, or some other kind of great danger or suffering.  If a farmer loses his whole crop and is in fear of starvation, and comes to buy grain, then the seller is suddenly in a position of power over him, able to use that fear as a lever.  If the seller does so, and ratchets up his prices absurdly high, it is hard to see how this does not count as a kind of coercion.  However, for reasons unknown to me, our free marketeers will treat this as a completely voluntary transaction, and one in which the laws of supply and demand should have free rein to set a reasonable price.  They might object that the farmer does not need to pay the unreasonable price–he can just go to another merchant.  If this were true, then we would have no problem.  But of course, it is very often not true. Businesses know how much greater coercive leverage they can gain if it is not true, and that is why monopoly is such a prized goal.

 Now generally such coercive power over buying has been restricted to absolute needs–if someone breaks their pencil and has to buy another, the seller is unlikely to be able to bring much of a fear motivation to bear.  Enter the power of modern marketing.  Marketing of course has many valid uses, but one key function of modern marketing has been to redress the limitation that only absolute needs can put a buyer in a coerceable position.  The solution, of course, is to increase the scope of absolute needs, since “needs” are largely a matter of perception.  Take me, for instance.  I would say that I need a regular supply of milk, eggs, bread, butter, meat maybe three times a week, some cheese, salt and pepper, at least a cup of coffee a day, preferably some tea as well, several sets of nice clothing, a computer, earbuds, several albums of music, a cell phone, a number of computer programs, a steady supply of new books, wireless internet access, a comfortable bed and blankets, and some basic hygiene supplies.  Clearly, most of these are not genuine absolute needs.  But the fact that I perceive them as such means that I am prone to fear if I do not have them, and thus prone to having that fear worked upon to persuade me to do things or pay prices that I rationally would not want to pay.  And of course I think I would be reasonable in saying that this is a fairly short list of needs compared to most young people in the modern West, who are fairly easily persuaded that they need iPods, iPhones, thousands of songs of music, a digital camera with at least ten megapixels, an almost endless supply of the latest and most fashionable clothing, along with various food and drink addictions, ranging from the grossest junk food to the faddiest health food.  Some of this need-creation is done by marketing working on our physical appetites–whether the lust of the flesh or the lust of the eyes–but the most powerful forms work on our emotional appetites–on the pride of life–and sometimes by creating or preying on fear.  Teenagers are probably the most vulnerable demographic, easily convinced that they will be a complete social failure if they do not buy any number of fashionable absurdities.  We would point out that most of these “needs” are illusory, but in some cases, that’s not quite true.  For instance, in the realm of business, most businesses now pretty much need to have a website–if a new device can be successfully marketed to the majority of businesses in an industry, then suddenly, the others will find that it has gone from being a luxury to a necessity if they want to stay competitive. 

Now, again, not all of this by any means is morally objectionable.  In the latter example–of businesses constantly having to upgrade–that’s just part of how the advance of technology works, and although we might legitimately argue in certain cases that technology ought to move a bit more slowly, it is not necessarily exploitation for the purveyors of such technology to make it so that everyone has to jump on board.  And in the former example, we would no doubt say that the insecure buyers bear plenty of responsibility for letting themselves be duped into “needing” luxuries.  However, it is crucial to note that the fact that there is fault on the one side does not mean there is none on the other.  If someone has an irrational fear of something, and I decide to play up their irrational fears and use them to convince them to do all sorts of things for me, then I am certainly guilty of a wicked kind of manipulation, and probably, given the definitions we have been working with, a subtle form of coercion.  I think that we are naive if we do not recognize that a kind of “coercion” may be going on when a clothing company convinces a girl to pay four times what a pair of jeans is worth because they have played up her fears that she will be rejected by everyone if she doesn’t buy them.

The point here, of course, is not to argue that all or even most modern marketing is “coercive,” or to deny that most needless purchasing decisions are still made out of a vices as simple as covetousness, rather than fear.  The point is simply to establish that we need to offer a more complex account of how the economic sphere really operates in our world, and such an account, it seems to me, must include an analysis of the various subtle and even overt kinds of coercion at work.  In the next segment, I will turn to try and offer a similarly complex account of the political sphere.

7 thoughts on “Coercion and Motivations in the Economic Sphere (Deconstructing Coercion, Pt. 3)

  1. I like this, but I'm not convinced you go far enough.First, I'm not sure coercion should be limited to fear. If I befriend someone, to get them to do something, I am coercing them. And it may be a particularly heinous form of coercion. Say an older man befriends a vulnerable young woman so he can sleep with her. He doesn't threaten to abandon her if she doesn't sleep with him, but just charms her into bed, and then leaves her on the street. She was taken advantage of, and coerced into his bed. Very nearly, she was raped. But she was coerced through love. (Thus making his crime particularly evil. He is a traitor against charity, and should be frozen in the ice.)Also, I'm not sure you push the element of love in economics far enough. Advertising is no longer predicated on satisfying desire, but on creating brand loyalty, and creating desire and need through mimesis–and mimesis is based on love.Finally, I think you perhaps downplay the degree of coercion companies can use. There's a reason "Sixteen Tons" ("I owe my soul to the company store") resonates, and it was lamenting a legitimate problem. In the West, such extreme coercion doesn't exist anymore, but it does in the rest of the world, and milder versions still exist.

    Like

  2. Brad Littlejohn

    Matt, You're quite right that I don't go far enough, and "downplay the degree of coercion companies can use." My purpose in these posts is to try to construct an argument that will be compelling hopefully across the board, and that means exercising restraint and not alienating opponents by indicting corporations for every relevant crime.I'm not sure if I agree with your first example though. While such treason against charity is of course quite wicked, I think we are stretching the definitions too far if we call it "coercion." I don't want to start lumping every form of manipulation, deception, and false persuasion under the heading "coercion" because pretty soon the concept will become useless if we do that. I want to stick with its formal definition and then explore all the implications of that definition. And that seems to mean that coercion requires an element of fear, not merely love. The category you have in mind seems to be "exploitation." Regarding the role of love, yes, this is very interesting stuff, and I would've liked to pursue it more. But as I said, I'm not trying to give a comprehensive account of human action, but to focus our attention primarily on the coercive aspects of it. Hopefully I can return to fill out the rest of the picture some other time.

    Like

  3. Yes. That makes sense.The one difficulty I have (with the second paragraph) is that even if she isn't coerced into his bed, she is, to some degree, compelled into his bed. She does not freely choose him. If you just want to talk about coercion, that's fine. But we readers should recognize that there is even more to compulsion besides coercion.

    Like

  4. Brad Littlejohn

    Yes, I think this is an interesting point to make. The lines between love and fear, just like those between reward and fear, actually prove to be rather grey at times. For instance, what if someone acts in a certain way because they know it will make their family happy and they value the good opinion of their family–are they acting out of fear of disapproval, or because they love their family? The same thing can happen on a community level. To decide in any particular case when healthy motivations prevail and when motivations of compulsion, coercion, or manipulation prevail perhaps will often depend upon the psychology of the individual, making it difficult to make sweeping judgments.

    Like

  5. Albert

    If someone acts in a certain way because they are afraid of the severe financial consequences of acting otherwise (in losing their job), how is this different from someone who acts in a certain way because they are afraid of the severe financial consequences of acting otherwise (in paying a steep fine)?

    I pretty much agree with what you're saying here, but I want to go a bit farther to engage free-marketeers. If there are free-marketeers who really believe the employee working out of a motivation of fear is not being coerced, they would likely reason, "Well, who's coercing the employee?" to which the (correct) reply might be "The employer." The free-marketeer would be confused because it doesn't feel like coercion to him, and the reason for that is because there's another dimension that is intertwined with coercion (to paraphrase what you say, persuasion through fear): the legitimacy of the coercion which is necessarily tied actual persons with authority.This example will clarify: if I am at the edge of a tall building's roof and look over the edge, I will persuaded by fear of falling to move back from the edge. Am I being coerced or in a coercive situation? Strictly and technically speaking, perhaps. I would be coerced by the laws of physics or survival instincts or something related. But, that's not typically seen as coercion because we (perhaps wrongly) conflate "coercion" with "illegitimate/unjust coercion by persons with some kind of authority." I think that's what's going on with free-marketeers who don't see an employee feeling motivated by fear of dismissal by the employer as "coercion" while the employee threatened with some government fine is seen as "coercion." It's kind of like the contemporary usage of "discrimination" with "unjust discrimination." This leads us to the question of differing conceptions of justice, e.g. why do we believe employees do not deserve particular jobs (justice as desert)? I'm favor acknowledging both the necessity and inadequacy of "justice" as a grounding of economic systems, except as a part of "love" because of the problems a justice/love dichotomy have in common with dichotomous nature/grace and spiritual/temporal schemes.

    Like

  6. Bradley

    Fyi, I just stumbled across an entry in the Merriam-Webster Legal Dictionary that explicitly lists the fear of being fired as an act of coercion:Main Entry: coercion Function: noun : the use of express or implied threats of violence or reprisal (as discharge from employment) or other intimidating behavior that puts a person in immediate fear of the consequences in order to compel that person to act against his or her will: see also DEFENSE, DURESS — compare UNDUE INFLUENCE

    Like

Leave a comment